Think Anomalous
  • Home
  • Videos
  • Articles
  • About
  • Support
  • Contact
  • Survey
  • Home
  • Videos
  • Articles
  • About
  • Support
  • Contact
  • Survey

​​

.

Seeing is Believing?

3/14/2016

2 Comments

 
Picture
Michael Shermer, science educator and debunker. Photo by Jeremy Danger.

A year or so ago, I came across Michael Shermer’s now famous article in Scientific American, “Anomalous Events that Can Shake One’s Skepticism to the Core.”(1) Shermer is best known as a popular debunker and founder of Skeptic magazine, but this article took a different tone. Shermer admitted to having witnessed an anomalous event that he could not explain; one that challenged his scientific skepticism.

The event was compelling enough. Immediately before Shermer’s wedding ceremony, his grandfather-in-law’s transistor radio, which had been broken for decades, spontaneously repaired itself and played love songs from the radio. It returned to its dysfunctional state the next day. 

Shermer’s admission that we was unable to account for the event is admirably scientific. The occurrence would be enough to convince anyone that there might be something real to anomalous phenomena, and I, for one, was thrilled to learn that a debunker as hard-nosed as Shermer was willing to reconsider his approach to the paranormal, if only on one case in particular.  

However, there’s something troubling about Shermer’s reaction to his experiences as well, and it reflects a wider issue in our society’s approach to the unexplained. 

What’s troubling is not so much that Shermer took notice of anomalous phenomena when he did, but that he never did so before, even while millions of others were reporting identical experiences; that Shermer only opened his mind to the reality of the paranormal when it happened to him directly, and not when it when happened to anyone else.


The Limitations of Direct Experience

Direct experience with an anomalous phenomenon is certainly valuable, and often enough to change anyone’s mind. But this “seeing is believing” brand of skepticism, however principled and conservative it may seem, rests on shaky epistemic foundations.

To hold direct observation as the standard for truth implies that those of us who never see an anomalous event for themselves will never truly have the grounds to reach a conclusion on its reality. If NDEs, for example, were truly “divine” experiences, then the select few who experience them would be the only ones to know it, and scientists everywhere would be forever blind to this intricate and mysterious facet of our consciousness.

But the idea that we should all just wait for a personal experience flies in the face of western science. Science is a system for reaching shared truths that even those with no direct experience of them should be able to accept with confidence. With a truly scientific approach, we should be able to establish a standard of evidence that wouldn’t require us all to spend countless hours under the stars for our own glimpse of a UFO. This is not the way that we reach our conclusions on any of the more mundane phenomena we might encounter in our lives, and it’s not the way that we should reach our conclusions on whatever we choose to define as the paranormal.

What’s more, the idea that your subjective reaction to a particular anomalous experience should carry any more weight than any one else’s is epistemologically unsound. All observers, trained or untrained, professional or amateur, are working with the same flawed pieces of human hardware, and are subject to the same cognitive delusions. However flattering, the notion that you could make an observation that is epistemically stronger than someone else’s is indefensible. 

What pull could one more assessment, as fallible as anyone else’s, possibly have on the collective judgment of thousands of first-hand witnesses who have already been forced to accept that anomalies are real? And why would anyone else who’s adopted the same “seeing is believing” standard for evidence accept your testimony, once you’ve had your own experiences? If everyone needed personal confirmation, there would be no way for you to convince anyone else of the truth once you’d found it for yourself. 

And yet, every time we dramatize scientific investigation of the unexplained, we focus an inordinate amount of time chasing UFOs in night-vision goggles, or provoking ghosts in haunted homes, looking for confirmation in a single, personalized observation. The result is always the same: no definitive conclusion can be established, and no conclusion ever will be. Observations on demand are a privilege afforded to researchers in some fields, but they can’t be relied upon in the field of anomalistics, and they are certainly not a prerequisite for a scientific investigation. There are other ways of assuring ourselves of the reality of anomalous phenomena, and it’s time we turned our focus to them instead. 


Moving beyond the Anecdotal
​

If Shermer is truly in support of a more open-minded, yet skeptical investigation of anomalous phenomena, then he needs to expand his data set beyond his own personal experience. We will never reach a sound conclusion on the basis of a single datum, and we will never prove the existence of an alleged phenomenon on the basis of a single encounter. It is the sum of our experiences together, and the weight of their volume and congruency, that give us the assurance that something objective is happening, and that we have not just succumbed to individual sensual errors. A descriptive phenomenology will do much more to advance our understanding than a good story, no matter how compelling. 

Given the fickle and unpredictable nature of most anomalous phenomena, there’s simply no way around our dependency on eyewitness testimony, flawed though it is. We’re going to have to learn to take witnesses seriously, and maybe establish a better standard for assessing their credibility. It’s just not scientific to ignore all eyewitness testimony (at least as it pertains to a certain range of phenomena) simply because it is not totally reliable. Denying certain claims wholesale and a priori is not an honest application of scientific skepticism; the kind that Shermer advocates elsewhere in his work.

We’ll never get anywhere in our study of anomalous phenomena if we wait around for personal confirmation. It is essential that we shed our irrational fear of accepting testimony of disquieting events, and learn from each others’ experiences. To deny the testimony of our peers is only to narrow our perception of the world, and to deny an important facet of our bizarre and intricate universe. ​

A personal experience is a transformative one, to be sure, and cause to “marvel in the mysterious,” as Shermer says. But this can’t be the only thing to turn us onto the unexplained. We need to move beyond the simple notion that seeing is believing. 


- Jason Charbonneau

​
​
1. Michael Shermer, “Anomalous Events That Can Shake One’s Skepticism to the Core,” Scientific American 311, no. 4 (2014). http://www.scientificamerican.com/article/anomalous-events-that-can-shake-one-s-skepticism-to-the-core/ (accessed February 16, 2016).

2 Comments
Jordan Edward
3/24/2016 06:07:54 pm

I largely agree with you, but, sometimes, one person's experience *can* change others' minds. I'm thinking something along the lines of the fallacy of authority (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Argument_from_authority).

The readers of Scientific American may be under the impression that only (to be facetious about it) addicts, the unemployed and hippies experience anomalies, in which case, to hear another example of such an experience from these sorts of people will fail to convince the readers of the merit of the experiences.

However, to hear that Michael Shermer, someone they presumably respect and in whom they place a great deal of trust, has had an anomalistic experience may persuade them that there's something more to it.

It speaks to the tribal nature of humanity, that we belief those who are more like us than we do those who are less like us. It's not scientific, unfortunately, but it's a reality.

Reply
Jason Michael link
4/16/2016 10:19:07 am

It's hard to argue that one person's experience *can* change others' minds, and I wasn't trying to deny this. No, it's not scientific, but yes, it is reality, and I accept that.

I was only trying to point out, as you do, that this in fact a fallacy, and that the fact that so many people rely on the opinions of people like Shermer to inform their views of anomalous phenomena is a sign of our culture's - and perhaps even our scientific educators' - regrettable scientific illiteracy.

I see how Shermer coming out and admitting to an anomalous experience is helpful, and again, I'm glad he did it, but the post was attempting to highlight the hypocrisy of his only doing so because the experience happened to him. For his entire career before this incident, Shermer, and too many others, immediately dismissed very similar (and often much more compelling) stories from other people. If there's a widespread belief that only people in the "lunatic fringe" have anomalous experiences, then Michael Shermer helped ensconce it in popular culture.

It seems that when other people have experiences, no amount of evidence is enough to convince him, and he'll go through all sorts of logical contortions to explain the event away as anything but what it appeared to be. But when he has the same kind of experience, even without a tenth as much of the supporting evidence, his "critical" faculties are dropped and the reality of the experience is essentially unquestioned (it's ironic to see how many "skeptics" have commented on Shermer's article to do exactly the sort of armchair debunking he's done to countless others).

This post is an attempt to diagnose a problem with our culture's epistemic assumptions and general understanding of science. My hope is that Shermer, if he ever reads this, will acknowledge the inconsistencies in his own epistemology, and take this as an opportunity to educate people on what should and should not count as evidence of a particular phenomenon. To me, that would mean admitting that we're all working with the same sensory hardware, and that one person's experience is no more reliable than any one others'. We have to learn to accept what other people are telling us about the world, even if those people don't have PhDs and tweed jackets. Waiting until it happens to you, or someone you respect, is unscientific, and will only ever impede our exploration of this intricate universe.

Reply



Leave a Reply.

    Picture

    Articles

    All Think Anomalous articles are written or edited by site founder and film maker, Jason Charbonneau. Jason is a freelance Foley artist and sound editor living in Toronto, Canada, and an anomalist by hobby.

    Picture

    Categories

    All
    Book Review
    Debunking Debunkers
    Evidence
    Intellectual Freedom
    Missing Persons
    Opinion
    Skepticism
    Terminology
    Theory And Method
    UFO

    Archives

    October 2016
    September 2016
    August 2016
    July 2016
    June 2016
    May 2016
    April 2016
    March 2016
    February 2016

    RSS Feed


    Picture
    Become a Patron
Picture
Copyright Think Anomalous, 2016 - 2023